"

2 Chapter 2 An Introduction to Arguments

Arguments consist of a set of statements, which are claims that something is or is not the case or is either true or false. The conclusion of your argument is a statement that is being argued for, or the point of view being argued for. The other statements serve as evidence or support for your conclusion; we refer to these statements as premises. It’s important to keep in mind that a statement is either true or false, so questions, commands, or exclamations are not statements. If we are thinking critically we will not accept a statement as true or false without good reason(s), so premises are key to constructing good arguments. Here are a couple of examples:

Example 1:
Capital punishment is morally justifiable since it restores some sense of balance to victims or victims’ families.

Let’s break this down into what is referred to as a standard argument form:

Capital punishment restores some sense of balance to victims or victims’ families.
Capital punishment is morally justifiable.

Example 2:
Because innocent people are sometimes found guilty and potentially executed, capital punishment is not morally justifiable.

Translating this argument to standard form looks like this:

Innocent people are sometimes found guilty and potentially executed.
Capital punishment is not morally justifiable.

When encountering an argument, one might inquire into how the conclusion was proven. As Dowden explains in Logical Reasoning, it is important to note that a proof means different things in different fields of study and in different situations. A proof in mathematics is going to have a higher standard than proving to your friend that you were at the same concert as she was last week. Essentially, “a proof is a convincing argument, an argument that should convince your audience, not simply an argument that does convince them.”

2.1 Statements

As noted above, statements are true or false. Here are a few examples of statements:

  • The Earth revolves around the Sun (True).
  • Humans can breathe in outer space without any special equipment (False).
  • Water boils at 100 degrees Celsius at sea level (True).
  • The Great Wall of China is visible from the Moon with the naked eye (False).
  • Heather ate chicken for lunch (unknown truth value).

All of these are statements—they are claims that are either true or false. We don’t need to know the statement to be true or to be false as long as it is possible to know. Statements should be differentiated from commands, suggestions, and questions. If someone says, “Shut the door,” “Let’s order a pizza,” or “Is it Tuesday?” they have not communicated a statement because none of these are true or false.

 

 

 

2.2 Arguments

While there are different definitions of the word argument, we will be using the term in a specific way. In philosophy an argument is a conclusion supported by premises. The conclusion and all of the premises of an argument are statements. Arguments range from simple to complex and some have only one premise while others have multiple premises. According to Dowden, the link between the premise(s) and the conclusion is called an inference. Here’s an example of a simple argument that has one inference step to the conclusion from two premises.

If it is snowing, we must shovel the sidewalk.
It is snowing.
We must shovel the sidewalk.

Dowden provides an analogy that might be helpful in our practice of determining whether an argument is present:

to find out whether an argument is present, you need to use your detective skills. Ask yourself whether the speaker gave any reason for saying what was said. If you get a satisfactory answer to your own question, then you probably have detected an argument, and you’ve uncovered its conclusion and premises. In detecting an argument, your main goal is to locate the conclusion, then the reasons given for that conclusion, while mentally deleting all the other sentences and phrases that are not part of the argument.

It is worth noting that some arguments will be more complex than others but breaking down an argument into smaller components (i.e. statements) will help you determine how a conclusion is supported.

 

 

Retired professor of philosophy, Dr. James Cain, developed an exercise book for logic students. In it he gives examples of simple and complex arguments.

Examples of simple arguments:

All humans are mortal. (premise)
Socrates is a human. (premise)
Thus, Socrates is mortal. (conclusion)

If the sun is out it is daytime. (premise)
The sun is out. (premise)
It is daytime. (conclusion)

Example of a complex argument:

If the sun is out then it is daytime. The sun is out. So it is daytime. The grocery store is open whenever it is daytime. So the grocery store is open.

This argument is formed by splicing two simple arguments, namely:

If the sun is out then it is daytime.
The sun is out.
So it is daytime.

It is daytime.
The grocery store is open whenever it is daytime.
So the grocery store is open.

2.3 Premise and Conclusion Indicators

Occasionally the terms we use in setting up an argument can offer tips to how the statements come together to form an argument. When reading a passage or listening to someone’s point of view, a good question to ask yourself is if you are being given reasons to convince you of something. If you think this is the case, identifying the conclusion and the reasons for accepting the conclusion is the next step. The terms used in an argument may include “therefore” or “consequently.” These two terms are used to convey conclusions. If we see terms like “because” or “since,” the author is likely trying to get us to understand the reasoning behind their claim, which is the premises. Here are lists of common conclusion and premise indicators:

Conclusion Indicators:                                             Premise Indicators:
therefore, so, consequently                                    because, since, given that
hence, thus, as a result                                            as, due to, for the reason that,
it follows that, accordingly,                                     for, in view of, assuming that
for this reason                                                           may be inferred from

There is no guarantee that an arguer will use one of these verbal cues and we have to recognize an argument without those tips. However, if they are present and helpful, use them!

 

 

2.4 Implicit Premises and Conclusions

It is not uncommon for an argument to contains what we call implicit premises and conclusions. This means that parts of the reasoning or the conclusion remains unstated. This usually happens when the claim or assumption within the argument is too obvious. Dowden gives us an example that shows an implied premises: “suppose a biologist argues that there is nothing ethically wrong in the fact that about thirteen animals per day are killed in her laboratory, because the deaths further her scientific research. In this argument, she uses the unstated assumption that, if something done to animals furthers someone’s scientific research, then it is not ethically wrong.” If an argument relies on an assumption that is part of our common sense or what is evident, then the assumption is often left unstated.

Unstated conclusions can also turn up in arguments. Dowden suggests the following scenario:

What is the implicit conclusion in the following argument? All insects have exactly six legs, but all spiders have exactly eight legs, so now what do we know about whether spiders are insects? You, the reader, have to figure out the conclusion for yourself: that spiders are not insects. People who are unwilling to do this detective work will miss the point of many passages.

Just as we can use indicator terms and detect unstated premises, we can detect implied conclusions.

 

 

2.5 Diagramming Arguments

We can produce a visual representation of an argument by using a technique called diagramming. This is also useful for helping us breakdown or analyze the statements that constitute the argument. Here are Dr. Cain’s examples:

Simple arguments

If an argument contains a single premise, then use an arrow to point from the premise to the conclusion.

Example: (1) Leo plays the guitar, so (2) he plays a stringed instrument.

1

2

 

If two or more premises are intended to work as a unit to support a conclusion, then join them together with a plus sign (+) and draw an arrow to the conclusion.

Example: (1) Leo plays the guitar well. (2) Nobody plays the guitar well unless they have practiced a lot. So (3) Leo has practiced a lot.

1+2

3

Complex Arguments

If two of more arguments lead to the same conclusion, then for each such argument there will be one arrow pointing to the numeral for the conclusion. This will happen when the reasons supporting the conclusion work independently.

Examples:
(1) It is snowing and (2) a very cold draft coming in under the door, so (3) it must be cold outside.

1                     2

    Bottom Right Arrow Action Position Vector Svg Png Icon - Arrow Pointing ...         Arrow Pointing Down Clipart , Free Transparent Clipart - ClipartKey

    3

(1) Leo must practice the guitar a lot. After all, (2) Leo plays the guitar well, and (3) nobody plays the guitar well unless he practices a lot. Besides, (4) Leo’s mother tells him to practice a lot, and (5) Leo always does what his mother tells him to do.

2+3              4+5

   Bottom Right Arrow Action Position Vector Svg Png Icon - Arrow Pointing ...        Arrow Pointing Down Clipart , Free Transparent Clipart - ClipartKey

      1

 

(1) Jeff told me that either Linda or Lloyd would be at the concert. (2) Lloyd told me that he would not be able to go. So (3) Linda must have gone. That means that (4) Linda will be able to tell you whether Leo was one of the performers.

1+2

3

4

 

(1) Leo must have played at yesterday’s concert since (2) he was in town yesterday and (3) he would not have come here unless he was going to play at the concert. (4) Wherever Leo plays the place is packed. So (5) the concert must have been crowded yesterday.


2+3

    1+4

    ↓

    5

Things to keep in mind when diagramming:

  • Check your work by looking at each arrow and asking whether what comes above the arrow really was intended to give support to what is below the arrow.
  • Pay attention to premise and conclusion indicators. A premise indicator shows that a statement comes before an arrow, and a conclusion indicator shows that it comes after an arrow.
  • Arrows should never point to plus signs. They should point to numerals which represent conclusions.

For extra practice with diagramming, see Exercise 1.5 at the end of this chapter.

 

Conclusion

With regard to determining whether an argument is a good one, we will later learn key tools to evaluate arguments. As Dowden pointedly claims, “the main objective in arguments is for the conclusion to follow its premises either with certainty or with high probability.” This takes us to the two general categories of arguments, deductive and inductive. Deductive arguments are those that aim to secure conclusions with certainty and inductive arguments are aiming to demonstrate the probability of the conclusion. The former is the focus of chapter 6 and the latter the focus of chapter 5.

 

 

Dowden, Bradley H. Logical reasoning. Accessed January 14, 2025. https://www.csus.edu/indiv/d/dowdenb/4/logical-reasoning-archives/Logical-Reasoning-2020-05-15.pdf.

Van Cleave, Matthew J. “Logic Text V 2.0.PDF.” Google Drive. Accessed January 14, 2025. https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B-rkbctcWjo3OFhGODNSYTZPMVU/view?resourcekey=0-iGfOufS0tNl2MRQa64ITng.

 

Exercise 2.5: Diagramming Arguments (Cain)

Identify the premise and conclusion indicators and diagram the following arguments. If a problem number is in bold print, the problem is answered in the back of this book.

1. (1) Linda must be home since (2) her car is in the driveway. Besides, (3) she told me that she would be home.

2. (1) Linda must be home already, since (2) she got out of school early today and (3) she always goes directly home after school.

3. (1) No one who understands how to wire a house would confuse a ground wire with a hot wire. (2) I saw Jones confuse the two. So (3) he must not know how to wire a house. So (4) if you need to hire someone to wire a house then you shouldn’t hire Jones.

4. (1) You should buy this car. (2) It is a great car to drive and (3) it will have a high resale value since (4) it is so popular.

5. (1) You should go see Alice because (2) she can help you. (2) She can help you since (3) she has had a lot of experience dealing with those sorts of problems.

6. (1) Ticks are arachnids. (2) Arachnids have four pairs of legs, but (3) the bug you found on your arm had only three. So (4) it wasn’t a tick.

7. (1) Paul has been acting different lately. (2) He used to be a very conscientious student, but (3) now he only comes to class occasionally. Furthermore, (4) he no longer eats with a fork or a spoon but uses his fingers instead.

8. I’m sure (1) you don’t have scurvy. (2) That’s a disease caused by a vitamin C deficiency, and (3) you get plenty of vitamin C, since (4) you eat so many oranges and (5) they have a lot of vitamin C.

9. (1) You must have never washed this sweatshirt of yours previously. (2) Before I washed it today, the arms were much too long, but (3) now its arms only go a few inches below your elbows. (4) No sweat shirt would shrink that much unless it had never been washed before.

10. (1) Either the cook or the chauffeur murdered the butler. Since (2) the cook was in town all day, (3) he could not have done it. So (4) the chauffeur must have done it.

11. (1) The bird we saw was either a common nighthawk or a whip-poor-will. (2) A nighthawk has pointed wings, whereas (3) a whip-poor-will has rounded wings. (4) The one we saw definitely had pointed wings. So (5) it was a nighthawk.

12. (1) Anyone who lives in the desert and doesn’t own a dependable car is a fool. (2) Susan lives in the desert; (3) she is no fool, and (4) she owns a Ford Pinto. Clearly then (5) a Pinto is a dependable car.

13. (1) Joe must be feeling pretty good, since (2) Linda said she would go out with him and (3) he has wanted to go out with her for a long time. Another reason is that (4) he just won the lottery.

14. (1) Judy is either a follower of Karl Marx or a follower of Groucho Marx. But (2) she can’t be a follower of Karl Marx since (3) she says that learning history is a waste of time and (4) no follower of Karl Marx would say that. So (5) she is a follower of Groucho.

15. (1) If the house caught fire because the wiring was bad, then the electrician was at fault. But (2) the electrician was probably not at fault since (3) he always double checks his work very carefully. So most likely (4) the fire was not due to faulty wiring.

16. (1) Our policy of using nuclear weapons as deterrents is a form of terrorism, for (2) the primary targets of our weapons are civilian populations, and (3) threatening the lives of innocents as a means of achieving one’s goal is terrorism. (4) Even if one’s goals are praiseworthy, one is never justified in pursuing those goals through terrorism. Therefore, (5) we are not justified in our policy of nuclear deterrence.

17. (1) She must have left the key down stairs, for (2) she said that she would either do that or leave the key in my mailbox. But I know that (3) she didn’t leave it in my mailbox since (4) my mailbox is on the eighth floor, (5) the elevator is broken, and (6) she hates to climb stairs.

18. (1) The burglars either came in through the basement door or they pried open the kitchen window. (2) If they had pried open the window it would have been damaged, but (3) it wasn’t. So (4) they must have come in through the basement. That means that (5) they must be highly skilled, since (6) the basement door had a lock that was very hard to open. So I conclude that, very likely, (7) the thieves were professionals.

19. We know that (1) the cook couldn’t have committed the crime since (2) witnesses saw her stirring the soup at the time of the crime. We also know that (3) the chauffeur couldn’t have done it since (4) a reliable witness claims to have seen him changing a flat tire at the time of the crime. Since we already know that (5) the culprit was the chauffeur, the cook, or the butler, we may conclude that (6) the butler did it.

20. (1) Cindy told me she was going to the store and then she left the house. But (2) I didn’t hear the car leaving. So (3) she must have walked to the store. (4) It would be too much for her to carry all the items on the grocery list. So (5) she will not be getting everything on the list.

21. We were able to conclude that (1) the rockslide occurred because of an earthquake which took place in the region. First, we know that (2) there was an earthquake in the region because (3) we have found that land masses near the rockslide shifted along a fault line. Second, (4) geologist tell us that no other forces were present at the time which could have led to the rockslide.

22. (1) No squirrel could have been in my apartment last night. (2) If one had been then Fido would have been barking, since (3) he always barks at squirrels. (4) But Fido was quiet all night. Furthermore, (5) I had all the holes through which squirrels could enter patched up.

23. (1) You should not complain and worry so much, given that (2) you really have a comparatively good life. (3) Life was much harder for our ancestors for example. (4) A couple centuries ago people didn’t have indoor plumbing; (5) travel was difficult, time consuming and dangerous; (6) general life expectancy was very short, and (7) no one had television.

24. (1) Death is one of two things: either it is an annihilation in which we have no consciousness at all, or it is a migration of the soul to another place. (2) If there is no consciousness, then death is a great gain. For (3) if the dead are without consciousness, then death is like a sound sleep in which we do not dream, and everyone would agree that (4) such sleep is a happy thing. On the other hand (5) if death is a migration of the soul then we will be able to meet those who have already died. (6) To meet them would be a wonderful experience. We see then that (7) death is not something that we should dread. [Based on Socrates’ speech in Plato’s Apology.]

 

Personhood Activity

definition

License

Logic and Critical Thinking Exercises Copyright © by wilburh. All Rights Reserved.